PART 1: REDUCTIONISM, CAUSE, AND IDENTITY
Chapter 1
CAUSAL CONDITIONS FOR CONTINUITY
INTRODUCTION
For the purposes of this chapter I am assuming
reductionism to have been established as a component of a theory of personal
identity or survival. This chapter will examine differing accounts of causal
conditions for personal continuity or identity and argue for one of them.
The
assumption of reductionism throughout the following can summarized as this: My
identity, survival, or continuity can be understood as reducible to certain
other facts; these are facts about psychological connectedness and continuity.[1] Parfit refers to these facts as the “R-relation.” I
am not something ontologically separable from the R-relation. The Reductionist
claim is: “A person’s existence just consists in the existence of a brain and
body, and the occurrence of a series of interrelated physical and mental
events.” (Parfit, 1984, p.211.)
Even
if we agree on Reductionism there are still a number of differing views of
personal identity available. I will set out these views in descending order of
how restrictive is the causal condition each one specifies. To clarify the
differences between the possible views I will provide five thought experiments
and will show the differential response of the theories to these cases. Further
clarification will come from setting out the different types of cause that can
support continuity of the R-relation and examining what assumptions each theory
makes about the various types of cause.
Finally,
I will provide several arguments in favor of the Conservative Interpretation of
the Widest Reductionist View (CIWR). My
conclusion will be that personal identity can survive the absence of normal,
reliable, or direct causal connections between one stage of a person and a
continuer. Some kind of causal
connection between stages of a person is required for them to count as stages
of a single individual. This chapter will provide a foundation for later
chapters of the dissertation which will examine transformation of self, i.e.,
various ways in which a self can change over time and the significance of these
changes, and how they may be assimilated into the self.
The
conception of the self being developed here Armstrong has called a relational
view (or what has been called a perdurance view), as opposed to an identity
view (or endurance view).[2] We can look at a person who persists over time and
divide up their life into any number of non-overlapping temporal stages or
phases. An identity view, in Armstrong’s sense, would hold that these phases
are identical with one another in some numerical sense. The identity view
treats temporal parts differently from spatial parts of a thing: Spatial parts
are clearly different parts of a particular, P; they are obviously not
identical with one another. (The asymmetry between the identity view’s
treatment of spatial and temporal parts provides grounds for an objection to
that view, according to Armstrong.) The relational view, by contrast, treats
spatial and temporal parts symmetrically. On the relational view,
non-overlapping phases of some perduring particular, P, are not identical in
any sense. These phases are simply different parts of the same thing. That
thing is constituted by those
temporal parts and their relations to each other and to other particulars. The
account of personal identity or continuity presented here is relational in this
sense. The self—the diachronic, continuant self—consists of its temporal stages
or phases and the relations between them. The particular relation, in this
case, is what Parfit calls the R-relation: Psychological connectedness and
continuity.
At this point it would be sensible
to explicitly stipulate how I shall be using the term “self”, before confusion
arises. Some people use the term to refer to the temporal phases or
person-stages of the continuant person. Others use it to refer to the
diachronic particular constituted by its phases and their relations. It is
especially important to define my usage since I am building on Parfit’s theory
of psychological reductionism, and so might be assumed to be following his
usage. Parfit sometimes presents his discussion of personal identity or
survival in terms of successive selves.[3] Looked at this way, the continuant person is made
up of, or can be regarded as, a series of successive selves. Any two temporally
contiguous selves are highly psychologically connected, whereas widely
temporally separated selves may be only very weakly connected. However, I will
not adopt this usage. I will use “self”
to refer to the continuant, perduring, diachronic individual. Its
constituent temporal parts I will refer to as person-stages, person-phases, or
phases of the self.
Perduring, continuant, diachronic person = SELF
Transient, temporal part of person =
PERSON/SELF-STAGE or PHASE
My
reason for preferring this usage will become more obvious as this chapter
proceeds. Essentially, I believe that the contrary usage—using “self” to refer
to the temporal phases—reflects and encourages too heavy a weighting of the
significance of these phases, and devalues the importance of the continuant
self. This difference in emphasis between my transformationist interpretation
of psychological reductionism and Parfit’s version will show up in the sections
on the importance of projects and values to the continuity of the person.
Apart from the unwanted emphasis on
the short term resulting from equating self with person-phase, such an equation
can easily give the misleading impression that there really are relatively
distinct selves. We may talk of the infant self, the child self, the adolescent
self, and the adult self, and think of the continuant self as the temporal
concatenation of these distinct and successive selves. Nevertheless, this
obscures the fact that we rarely find anything resembling a clear line or
sudden transition from one such ‘self’ to another. Those four terms are merely
loose references to person-phases; the borders they draw can be arbitrarily
moved around with some latitude. For instance, we may draw the line marking the
change from the adolescent self to the adult self at 13 years (as do Jews and
some other cultures), or at 16, or 18, or 21, or the age (whatever it turns out
to be) when some specified qualities have been developed.
Instead of talking in terms of
successive selves, I shall stick with the more basic language of degrees or
extent of psychological connectedness. If I need to refer to earlier or later
instances of a person, I will also use the terms self-stage or self-phase (or person-phase).
In other words, I will replace a series of successive selves with a spectrum of
connectedness. Connectedness can be measured in two ways giving different
answers though, in common with everyone else, I will use the first way. The two
ways differ in what to use as the standard of connectedness degree. The first
and obvious way is to ask how much of the earlier phase (A) survives or
continues on in the later phase (B). (Rather than earlier and later phases, A
and B could be original and duplicate selves.) Take the case (illustrated in
Figure 3 below) where half of A’s characteristics are shared by B. B, in
addition, has a great many characteristics not shared by A. According to the
first way of measuring connectedness, A and B are 50% connected (or A is 50%
connected to B). Another way to say this is that 50% of A is subsumed in B. The
second way measures connectedness in terms of B. We would then describe Figure
3 as a case where connectedness was very low (say 1%) because A has only 1% of
B’s characteristics. When A and B represent earlier and later selves (as they
will throughout this chapter), only the first way of measuring seems useful.
However, If A and B are taken to be an original self and a copy, the second way
will be useful, especially when B thinks about the situation. Henceforth, I
shall be assuming connectedness is measured the first way, in terms of the
earlier self.
Determining the degree of connectedness will not
suffice to tell us all that we need to know about our earlier and later phases
if we (earlier phase) are to make sensible decisions about allocating present
vs. future costs and benefits. The same degree of connectedness may attach to
situations that are not equally desirable. Knowing only that self-phases A and
B are 50% connected (for example) leaves out much information about our
relation to the later phase. The statement that A and B
DIAGRAM HERE
DIAGRAM HERE
are
50% psychologically connected could represent any one of three possible
propositions (each of which are represented in the diagrams):
(1) B has 50% of A’s
characteristics, but no characteristics that A doesn’t have, i.e. B is a subset
of A. (Figure 1)
(2) B has 50% of A’s
characteristics, and 50% of B’s characteristics are not shared by A. (Figure 2)
(3) B has 50% of A’s
characteristics, and only a small fraction of B’s characteristics are shared by
A. (Figure 3)
We can use set diagrams to clarify
the ways in which two individuals may be psychologically connected. A and B may
stand for the earlier and later person-stages of a continuant individual (and
this is the interpretation I will be using). However, A and B could also
represent two individuals, each of whom is a survivor of the original. B could
be a copy of A—a copy of more or less fidelity, or who has psychologically
diverged over time from A.
In Figure 1 the earlier self-phase,
A, possesses all the characteristics of the later phase, B, but B has only 50%
of the characteristics of A. In this case, the later self-phase is a degenerate
continuer of A. B has learned nothing new, acquired no new memories, formed no
new intentions or dispositions, and values only what A valued, yet has lost
half of what made A who he was. In Figure 2, the later self-phase retains 50%
of A’s characteristics, but also has about as many new characteristics. In
Figure 3, the later self-phase retains 50% of A’s characteristics, but these
are now an insignificant fraction of B’s total psychological features. This
situation might be realized if A is an infant and B an adult self, or if A is any
person of today and B a person who, due to advances in gerontology, has lived
for many centuries (or their subjective equivalent[4]). B has added many new experiences and memories,
and acquired additional dispositions, abilities, and values.
Each of these three represents a
case of 50% connectedness. Nevertheless practically all of us would prefer our
future to turn out more like the situation in Figure 2 than in Figure 1, and
most of us would prefer Figure 3 to Figure 2. Many accounts of psychological reductionism
suggest or imply that it makes most sense to allocate our concern for our
future self-phases proportionally to the degree of connectedness. The three
cases just described show this to be implausible. The same degree of
connectedness may be arrived at in differing ways, and we will prefer some of
these to others. The relationship between the metaphysical degree of
connectedness and the normative degree of reasonable concern for later stages
is thus not a straightforward one. In the later chapter on “A Transformationist
Account of Continuity” I will propose several reasons for concerning ourselves
with our future phases more than proportionally to the degree of connectedness.
Having
clarified what I mean by connectedness, I will now set out several versions of
Psychological Reductionism and explore how they differ in regard to the causal
conditions they assume. Without an account of the causal conditions necessary,
we will not know when to say that a psychological connection has endured at
all.
FOUR THEORIES
FOUR THEORIES
The four theories explained here can be thought of
as placed along a spectrum of restrictiveness with regard to required causal
conditions. The first theory requires the cause of psychological continuity to
be a normal one, other theories relax this restriction, and the fourth theory
denies the need for any causal connection between a self and its continuer.
All
four Reductionist theories accept the Psychological Criterion. In order to
define this, let us review its components. Psychological
connectedness is the holding of particular direct psychological connections
such as memory links, the connection between intention and action, and enduring
dispositions. Psychological continuity
is the holding of overlapping chains of strong
connectedness.[5] Strong connectedness holds when “the number of
connections, over any day, is at least half the number of direct connections
that hold, over every day, in the lives of nearly every actual person.” (206)
The Psychological Criterion: (1) There
is psychological continuity if and only if there are overlapping chains of
strong connectedness. X today is one and the same person as Y at some past time
if and only if (2) X is psychologically continuous with Y, (3) this continuity
has the right kind of cause, and (4) there does not exist a different person
who is also psychologically continuous with Y. (5) Personal identity over time
just consists in the holding of facts like (2) to (4).[6]
THE NARROW REDUCTIONIST VIEW: We might also call
this the “Spatiotemporal Continuity view.” The Narrow Reductionist accepts the
Psychological Criterion but construes condition (3) narrowly. On this view, the
right kind of cause is the normal cause. The normal cause is the continued
existence of the brain since our psychological features depend on our brain
states. The Narrow Psychological Criterion virtually always coincides with
another reductionist view—that of the Physical Criterion. The Physical
Criterion says that “a person continues to exist if and only if (a) there
continues to exist enough of this
person’s brain so that it remains the brain of a living person, and (b) no
different person ever has enough of this person’s brain.”[7] The Narrow Psychological Criterion and the Physical
Criterion differ in principle in that the former requires, in addition to the
two conditions of the Physical Criterion, that there is psychological
continuity, that it has its normal cause, and that no one else is
psychologically continuous with the person.
THE WIDE REDUCTIONIST VIEW: (Or “Closest Functional
Continuer with a Reliable Cause.”) This also accepts the Psychological
Criterion but holds that the “right cause” is any reliable cause and not
necessarily the normal one. If the memories, intentions, and dispositions that
together comprise the R-relation were to be sustained by some reliable process
other than the normal activity of the brain, the Wide View would say that
identity had been preserved. For example, memory could be preserved on this
view by substituting a mechanical replacement for a collection of neurons so
long as no change in function occurred. Or, an example from Nozick:
As you are dying, your brain
patterns are transferred to another (blank) brain in another body, perhaps one
cloned from yours. The patterns in the new brain are produced by some analogue
process that simultaneously removes these patterns from the old one… On
completion of the transfer, the old body expires.[8]
Here there is no physical continuity of the brain
and an abnormal cause is operating to sustain R-relatedness. The Narrow
Reductionist View would say the later individual was not the same person as the
original, whereas the Wide View says that they are the same.
Nozick’s
Closest Continuer Theory can be seen as a variant on the Wide Reductionist
View.[9] The Closest Continuer theory says that something at
t2 is the same entity as X at t1 only if it is X’s closest continuer, is a
close enough continuer and is enough
closer than any other continuer. The only significant difference between the
Closest Continuer View and the Wide Reductionist View concerns Parfit’s fourth
condition for the Psychological Criterion. This said that “there does not exist
a separate person who is psychologically continuous with Y.” This is included
to rule out cases which violate the condition for transitivity of identity. If
person X at t1 is R-related to both Y and Z at some later
time t2,
then, according to Parfit’s account of the Psychological Criterion, X cannot be
identical to either Y or Z even if, at a still later time t3 there is only one person R-related to X.
The
Closest Continuer theory, by contrast, might allow Z to be identical to X
despite there having been a period in which both Y and Z were continuers of X.
Nozick’s example is as follows:
Half of an ill person’s brain is
removed and transplanted into another body, but the original body plus
half-brain does not expire when this is being done; it lingers on for one hour,
or two days, or two weeks. Had this died immediately, the original person would
survive in the new body, via the transplanted half-brain which carries with it
psychological similarity and continuity. However, in the intervening hour or
days or weeks, the old body lives on, perhaps unconscious or perhaps in full
consciousness, alongside the newly implanted body.[10]
If the old body had died simultaneously with the
transplantation, the new body plus half-brain would be the closest continuer.
However, so long as the original body plus half-brain remains alive it is the closest continuer. After it
dies, the new body plus half-brain becomes the closest continuer. As Nozick
asks, “Can its [the old body] lingering on during the smallest overlapping time
interval, when the lingerer is the closest continuer, mean the end of the
person, while if there was no such lingerer, no temporal overlap, the person
would live on. It seems so unfair for a person to be doomed by an echo of his
former self.”
Nozick
then offers several possibilities, one of which is that the person moves from
the original body to the new body not when the transplant occurs but when the
old body dies. (The reasonableness of this view is supported by Nozick’s
previous examination and rejection of condition that the identity of Y at t2 with X at t1 depends only on the properties and relations
of X and Y and not also on whether there exists a Z which more closely
continues X.)
Nozick
does not conclude that this is the right answer; rather he claims that a
certain indeterminacy is inherent in identity ascriptions. Our choice in this
case depends on whether we structure the concept of identity locally or
globally. We needn’t be concerned here with these complications. We can simply
note that a Closest Continuer view might allow identity to continue despite
some temporal overlap during which there are two close continuers. Of course,
if the old body lingered for several years before expiring we would not say
that the new body plus half-brain was a close enough continuer (since it would
have been going its own way for too long). There seems to be no clear way of
saying how long of an overlap is just too much for the new body plus half-brain
to count as identical with X.
If
the Closest Continuer theory is taken to allow some degree of temporal overlap
then this will conflict with Parfit’s fourth condition for the Psychological
Criterion which disallowed any separate person to also be psychologically
continuous with the original person. With this one difference however, the
Closest Continuer theory and the Wide Reductionist view can be made compatible.
If both theories accept a psychological criterion then, with the possible
exception of the overlap case, they will come to the same.
THE CONSERVATIVE INTERPRETATION OF THE WIDEST
REDUCTIONIST VIEW (CIWR): (Or: “Closest Functional Continuer with an Indirect
or Unreliable Cause.”) The Widest Reductionist View interprets the “right
cause” third clause of the Psychological Criterion as allowing any cause. So long as the later
continuer is caused to occur in some way, and the earlier stage of the person
plays a crucial role, even if indirect and unreliable, then the continuer
counts as the same person as the earlier person. An example will be given below
to illustrate what this might mean.
THE EXTREME INTERPRETATION OF THE WIDEST
REDUCTIONIST VIEW (EIWR): (Or: “Closest Functional Continuer with No Cause.”)
This actually subsumes two theories, the distinction between which will be
illustrated by the fourth and fifth cases below. The two possibilities depend
on what “No cause” is taken to mean. What they both have in common is that they
allow identity to continue even though the earlier stage plays no causal role
at all in the creation of the qualitatively identical later entity.
“No
cause” might mean (a) as just stated, that the earlier entity in no way causes
its qualitatively identical successor; however, the successor is caused to
exist by something, albeit something unrelated to the earlier entity; (b) the
most radical interpretation of the Extreme Interpretation of the Widest View
holds that Y can be identical to X so long as Y is qualitatively identical to
X, even though (i) X played no causal role in bringing about Y; and (ii) nothing caused Y to come into existence,
i.e., Y came about purely randomly. Though these two variants of the Extreme
Interpretation differ in principle, they are extremely unlikely to ever differ
in practice, and just about everyone will have the same intuitive responses to
both. I include both variants for the sake of completeness.
The following five cases or thought experiments are
intended to illustrate the differences between the theories and between
different views of the role of causation in the criteria of personal identity.
I will refer to them throughout the remainder of the paper, sometimes by their
abbreviations: 1:MBT; 2:TT; 3:AHR 4:OPR; 5:LPU.
1: My Brain Transplant: My life is
threatened with an as-yet incurable disease. My doctor advises me to have a
brain transplant. Cell samples are taken and a decerebrated clone grown at an
accelerated pace. My brain is transplanted to the new body and hooked up to it.
I am soon walking around in a healthy new body, free of the disease.
2: The Transporter: I step into a
We-Beam-U-Quick booth in Los Angeles. My body is scanned and the position and
velocity of all my constituent atoms and molecules determined and recorded. The
material of my body is atomized—far too rapidly for me to feel anything—and the
information specifying the structure of my body is transmitted to Tokyo. A
similar booth in Tokyo receives this information and constructs a body exactly
like the old one, except that new atoms (but of the same elements) are used. I
walk out of the booth happy to have made it so quickly to Japan, avoiding the
crush at the airports still used by conservative folk afraid of temporary
disintegration.
3: A Heroic Reconstruction: In 2330AD a
group calling itself the Order of Universal Immortalism (OUI) declares that its
centuries old ambition is finally realizable. Technology has rendered death a
matter of choice. Yet, they claim, the death of people in past centuries is
still a tragedy that ought to be remedied. Fortunately Personality Tracking and
Reconstruction Technology has matured to the point where it is now possible to
reconstruct their personalities. Into a Super-Reconstructor Computer is fed
information gleaned from the brains of people who knew the unfortunate persons,
in addition to the results of extremely complex tracing of causal connections
back in time. The 22nd century overthrow of quantum mechanics with its
uncertainty principle and replacement by Quantum Super-Determinacy, has allowed
(with the aid of vast computational power) the precise determination of the
state of the universe at all past times. OUI scientists recently successfully
reconstructed the information uniquely specifying the personality of a
previously deceased person and embodied that information in a living body. The
reconstructed person, Francis Bacon II, expressed surprise at finding himself
in the 24th century, but was pleased to see that his scientific method had been
able to accomplish so much.
4: Omega Point Resurrection: As
proposed by Frank Tipler,[11] at some vastly distant time in the future, our
distant descendents, now in control of all matter and energy in the universe,
set about resurrecting the dead. To ensure reconstruction of everyone who ever
lived, despite the loss of traces of most of them, they create duplicates of every possible person. One of these
duplicates is exactly like Francis Bacon, all the way down to his quantum
states, as he was shortly before he died.
5: The Luckiest Person in the Universe:
From our Los Angeles correspondent: They say that L.A. is the city where dreams
come true. But even hardened Angeleno’s were stunned by what happened today in
front of City Hall during a press conference. In plain view of a crowd of
people, and recorded by numerous cameras, a man identifying himself as Francis
Bacon, materialized out of nothing. Investigators have ruled out any trickery
and have been unable to explain this man’s appearance. “Bacon” has an appearance
in keeping with historical records and has offered details of the historical
character’s life and many detailed historical facts which have impressed
historians specializing in the area. One physicist has suggested that, although
such an event is extremely unlikely to occur even once in billions of years, it
is possible that Mr Bacon is the outcome of a completely random and
acausal quantum process. Atoms in the area might
have just happened to have simultaneously randomly changed state in such a way
as to produce this mysterious man.
The four theories outlined above can be
distinguished more clearly by showing how they handle these five cases. The
Narrow Reductionist View will allow that there is continuity of personal
identity in My Brain Transplant, but
in no other case. Continuity of the brain is the normal cause of psychological
continuity and a brain transplant preserves the brain. In the other four cases,
the brain—as a physically continuous entity—does not endure.
The
Wide Reductionist View would agree that identity survives the brain transplant,
but would go further in making the same judgement in The Transporter case. In this second case, the R‑relation is
preserved by an abnormal though reliable cause. The brain structures embodying
personality are transferred to a newly constructed brain by means of an
automatic process that reliably preserves the original patterns. (If this were
to become common practice, would the Narrow View come to regard it as a normal
means of continuity? If so, does that mean that transporters, when uncommon,
fail to preserve identity but do preserve it once they are used regularly?) The
Closest Continuer version of the Wide View might allow identity to have
continued even if the old brain had not been disassembled immediately upon
creation of the new brain at the remote location.
The
Wide Reductionist would describe the case of A Heroic Reconstruction as one where Francis Bacon ceased existing,
and later a different person just like him appeared. The Wide Reductionist
requires a reliable cause to operate
in maintaining R‑relatedness. As discussed below, this third case involves
decisions being made by other people such that the continuation of R‑relatedness
is precarious and is not governed by a reliable process. The fourth and fifth
cases go further in the direction of unreliability and so would not be accepted
as instances of the persistence of personal identity by the Wide Reductionist.
The
Conservative Interpretation of the Widest Reductionist View (CIWR) would hold
that personal identity had continued in the first three cases. Since this
theory requires for personal identity only that there be some causal relation between the earlier stage and the later one,
whether normal, reliable, or unreliable, Francis Bacon has continued on as the
same person in A Heroic Reconstruction.
The new Bacon is qualitatively identical to the historical Bacon, and the later
Bacon’s existence is dependent on the existence and qualities of the earlier
Bacon. The Universal Immortalists recreated Bacon because of his previous
existence, and they made him the way they did because of the way he was. CIWR
would describe the situation as one in which Francis Bacon jumped through time
from the 17th Century to the 24th, in principle just as if he had been in a
coma for seven centuries.
Despite
the apparent looseness of its causal condition for identity, CIWR would reject
the last two cases as instances of continuation of the same person. Although
qualitative identity is maintained in Omega
Point Resurrection and The Luckiest
Man in the Universe the earlier Bacon plays no role either in the coming
into existence or the qualitative identity of the second Bacon.
The
Extreme Interpretation(s) of the Widest Reductionist View (EIWR) counts the
first four cases as instances of the same person continuing. They require only
that the later Bacon-like individual be qualitatively identical (or
sufficiently similar) to the earlier. No causal connection between the earlier
and later Bacons is necessary. I should note here that if Bacon II is
qualitatively the same as the original Bacon just before he died, there will be
some overlap. On the Closest Continuer variant of the Extreme Interpretation
this breakdown in transitivity does not disrupt identity. According to Parfit’s
version in which identity requires that “there does not exist a different
person who is also psychologically continuous with Y”, the matter is open to
interpretation. Since in the example as described, there is no actual temporal overlap, Parfit’s condition has
been fulfilled and identity is maintained. However the spirit of Parfit’s
fourth, no-overlap, condition may disallow even the non-temporal overlap. If
so, then we could redescribe the cases such that Bacon II is created in the
same state that the original Bacon had just died in, and then returned to
consciousness. Alternatively, we can throw out the no-overlap condition and
regard the Extreme Interpretation as an account of personal continuity (Parfitian survival) rather
than identity.
The
Moderate interpretation of EIWR (M-EIWR) differs from the Radical
interpretation of EIWR (R-EIWR) over the fifth case. M-EIWR requires that there
be a cause of the later Bacon, though it need not be a cause relating the
earlier to the later person. R-EIWR rejects even this causal condition,
requiring only qualitative
continuity. R-EIWR holds that the randomly created Bacon in The Luckiest Man in the Universe is the
same person as the historical Bacon. I will argue below that there is no
important difference between M-EIWR and R-EIWR in practice, and little
theoretical difference.
All the theories examined here are reductionist.
Where they disagree is over the type or necessity of causation in personal
identity. In order to decide between the theories it will therefore be helpful
to more precisely distinguish the different types of cause at issue. After
setting these out I will give five arguments in favor of abandoning all but the
weakest causal condition. This will support a view as radical as the
Conservative Interpretation of the Widest View (which requires an indirect
cause of any kind), but not the Extreme Interpretation.
Causes
can set out along three spectra: (1) From normal
to any reliable to any to no cause. (2) From internal
to external. (3) According to degree
of directness: From direct to indirect to independent cause.
(1) (a) Normal Cause: The requirement
of a normal cause is embodied in the Narrow Reductionist View. The Physical
Criterion would take this to mean the standard continuity of a human brain. The
Psychological Criterion would add other, more complicated, conditions such as a
coherent development of later psychological traits out of earlier traits.
Continuity of the brain, considered on a gross level, is an insufficient
specification of a normal cause on the Psychological Criterion since the brain
may continue but its states might be radically disrupted in a way that
introduces a sudden and permanent change in personality. This might come about
as a result of some neurochemical shock, or due to an intense psychological
shock.
Clearly
the Narrow Reductionist has to make choices about what is to count as a normal
cause of psychological continuity. Some might count a sudden and profound
psychological change caused by the interaction of intensive “brain-washing”
with the existing personality as sufficiently abnormal to destroy personal
identity while others might not.
Another
question to be answered by the Narrow theorist is whether or not “normality” is
to be temporally indexed: Does “normal” mean “normal for 1990”, “normal up to
1990”, or “normal considering past, present, and future”? The problem is that
what is normal now may not always be so. A few hundred years ago, the normal
cause of good vision was having good natural eyes and no good vision existed
where eyes were faulty. Now, however, good vision is caused almost as often by
artificial devices and processes such as glasses, contact lenses, radial
keratotomy (and soon corneal sculpting). Perhaps one day unaltered brains will
not be the normal cause of psychological continuity. Just as we now often
replace other faulty organs with artificial organs, we might eventually replace
parts of the brain with functionally equivalent artificial parts (biological or
mechanical), and perhaps even the entire brain might be replaced (gradually
over time or all at once) with an artificial brain. If this were to occur would
the Narrow Reductionist say that the new method was an abnormal cause and
didn’t continue identity, or would she say that it is what is currently normal that counts? If the
latter, then why should we talk of a normal cause at all? Why not require
simply any reliable cause? Such indeterminacy in the normality condition strongly
suggests that this view is parochial and inessential.
(b) Any Reliable Cause: This is the condition minimally required by the
Wide Reductionist View (and Nozick’s version of the Closest Continuer Theory).
A reliable but abnormal cause is illustrated by The Transporter (if we assume either that transporters are unusual
or that “normal” refers to historically normal). In the transporter case
psychological continuity is reliably maintained since the process is (by
hypothesis) both automatic and about as reliable as the brain in ensuring
continuity.
To
be fanciful: Suppose that we are mistaken in our materialistic view that our
brains’ operations are determined by physical law and that in fact the
appearance of causal connectedness has always been brought about by “God.”
(That is, suppose God sustains the universe in existence rather than merely
having created it with the property of self-sustenance.) The normal and
reliable cause of psychological continuity is then God’s intentions and power
(assuming that God has a long-term intention to maintain standard operations).
One day God decides that he is bored with existing and decides to cease
existing. However, he feels responsible to his creation (or emanation) and so
changes the nature of the universe so that it is now self-sustaining just as we
materialists[12] always thought it was. The new cause of our
psychological continuity is not (yet?) the normal cause but it is just as
reliable as the old cause. The Wide Reductionist view sees this case as unproblematically
one where the reliable but non-normal cause is sufficient for continuity of
personal identity.
(c) Any Cause: This is illustrated by A Heroic Reconstruction and is the minimal causal requirement of
the Conservative Interpretation of the Widest View (CIWR). More accurately this
condition says: “Any relevant and sufficient cause connecting the earlier
entity with the later qualitatively identical entity.” This condition is less
demanding than the normal or any reliable causal conditions since the relevant
cause need be neither normal nor reliable. The dropping of these two conditions
is shown by A Heroic Reconstruction.
Here the new Bacon is clearly produced by a very abnormal cause. The causal
connection between the old and new Bacons is unreliable since it is mediated by
the intentions of other agents. If the Universal Immortalists had held
different beliefs and/or desires then the new Bacon would not have come into
existence.
Though
the requirements of normality and reliability are dropped on the “any cause”
view, there remains the requirement that there be a causal connection between
the earlier person and the later one. Nor can this be just any causal
connection. In the case of Omega Point
Resurrection, imagine that the second Bacon happened to pick up some old
writing of the earlier Bacon. The later Bacon then carries out an unfulfilled
intention expressed in that writing. This kind of connection would not be
sufficient for continuity of personal identity on the “any cause” view. In this
example, though there is a causal connection between the earlier and later
Bacons, it has nothing to do with the existence or qualitative identity of the
later Bacon (who was produced without any knowledge of the original). The “any
cause” condition requires that the causal connection be one necessary to
explain the coming into existence of the qualitatively identical later person
and sufficient to explain the qualitative similarity of the later person.
(d) No Cause: This drops even the requirement that the earlier entity
be causally connected in any way to the later one. This corresponds to the
Extreme Interpretation of the Widest View. There is a moderate and radical
version of the “no cause” view corresponding to the Moderate and Radical
interpretations of the Extreme Interpretation of the Widest View (M-EIWR and
R-EIWR). The radical interpretation takes “no cause” to mean not only that
there is no relevant cause connecting the earlier and later qualitatively
identical persons but also that there need be no cause of the later person at
all, i.e., the person could have come into existence without necessitating
prior causes.
(2) Internal to External: An internal
cause of personal continuity is a cause operating within the physical system
that instantiates the person. The continuation of psychological relatedness
over time when supported by the continued internal operations of the brain is a
case of an internal cause. Internal causes are likely to be normal causes, but
there could be abnormal internal causes such as the gradual replacement of
brain tissue by artificial components.
An
external cause exists where the continuity of personality results from
something other than the internal workings of the physical support system, such
as in The Transporter. If the
continuation of my personality depended on continual acts of God (as in some
interpretations of Berkeley’s views) then it would have an external cause.
The
point of distinguishing a reliability spectrum from an internality-externality
spectrum is that, for many people considering the cases, an internal unreliable
cause is much less disturbing than an external unreliable cause. Suppose a new
disease became epidemic; in most persons this disease leads to rapid
deterioration of neural function, thereby destroying personality. Although the
brain in such a situation would not be a reliable cause of psychological
continuity, few would feel that the identity of those not succumbing to the disease was threatened. By contrast, the case
of A Heroic Reconstruction, which could be no less reliable a cause of
continuity than exists in the diseased-brain society, will lead far more people
to doubt the continued identity of persons. Doubts about continuity of identity
increase independently with both increasing unreliability and increasing
externality of causes.
(3) The Directness of a Cause: This is
likely to be related to its reliability. Directness specifies how many steps
are necessary to the process that continues the qualitative identity. The more
steps there are ceteris paribus the
less reliable the cause of continuity will be. However, other factors may not
be equal. If the technology and construction of transporters were excellent,
then the indirectness of continuation by transporter may be no less reliable
than continuity resulting from normal brain operation.
A
direct cause need not be normal: So long as the earlier state of the physical
system supporting personality directly leads to the next state of the system it
doesn’t matter whether the system is the normal one. A partially computerized
brain might just as directly cause later states of the system.
An
indirect cause (as in The Transporter
and A Heroic Reconstruction) may or
may not involve actions on the part of other persons. If actions and decisions
of others are required in order to maintain continuity then the cause will
probably be more indirect and less reliable. The cause of continuity will
become increasingly indirect as more agents must decide whether to participate
in maintaining a person’s continuity. Every time continuity depends on
someone’s decision, the unreliability of the continuity increases. An
independent cause is the same thing as the moderate interpretation of “no
cause.” In this case the continuer of the earlier person has a cause that is
entirely unrelated to the earlier person.
The
foregoing suggests that the directness spectrum is not as deep as the
reliability or internality-externality spectra. Degrees of directness can be
reduced to combinations of degrees of reliability and internality/externality
(especially the former) whereas the latter two spectra cannot usefully be
reduced to each other.
The foregoing has consisted of conceptual
clarification and differentiation. I want to distinguish the various views as
sharply as possible in order to see precisely what is at issue between them.
Almost everyone (every reductionist at least) will be satisfied that personal
identity is secured so long as the normal continuity of the Narrow View is
maintained. But beyond that point intuitions differ over where the cut off
point lies. Some will reject The
Transporter case though most reductionists are willing to accept that as
preserving personal identity. Quite a few will draw a line between The Transporter, with its unusual but
reliable and fairly direct cause on the one hand, and all the later cases on
the other. Others will feel that the first three cases go together since there
is some important causal connection between the earlier and later persons. Very
few people will react differently in comparing Omega Point Resurrection and The
Luckiest Man in the Universe. I will provide several arguments that
together I take to strongly support the supposition that personal identity
exists in at least the cases of My Brain
Transplant, The Transporter, and A Heroic Reconstruction. Before arguing
that we should be willing to go as far as AHR and the Conservative
Interpretation of the Widest Reductionist View, I will argue that we should not
abandon all causal conditions. That is, we should reject the Extreme
Interpretation of the Widest Reductionist View. Omega Point Resurrection and The
Luckiest Man in the Universe are cases in which personal identity is not
maintained.
According
to the Widest Reductionist View any
causal connection that preserves connectedness is sufficient for the very same
individual to continue. I distinguished two variants of this view—the
Conservative and Extreme Interpretations. The Extreme Interpretation allows
“any cause” to include no cause. That
is, psychological connectedness may persist over a causal discontinuity. This
section will argue against the Extreme Interpretation of the Widest
Reductionist View.
My view, like Parfit’s, is that it
is the effect rather than the kind of cause that matters in these cases. Thus
radically different mechanisms like brain transplants, teletransportation, or
personality reconstruction (as in A
Heroic Reconstruction) can maintain the connectedness necessary to personal
continuity and identity. As I will show (mostly in the final chapter), some
kinds of changes and causes of changes are more compatible than others with a
judgment that the same person continues. If we meet a friend whom we have not
heard from in ten years, and we are startled by the enormous difference in
their personality, it will matter to us how they became who they are now. If
they developed into their current self in normal ways we will not hesitate to
believe they are numerically identical with the person we used to know (or:
this stage is a continuer of the person-stage we used to know). If we discover
that the personality of the friend we once knew was destroyed and replaced with
an implanted persona (as portrayed in the movie Total Recall and Phillip Dick’s original story “We Can Remember It
For You Wholesale”), we may not regard the former person as having survived.
Although I take a liberal view of
the kinds of underlying causes necessary for the same person to continue to
exist, I must challenge Daniel Kolak and Raymond Martin’s no-cause view in
“Personal Identity and Causality: Becoming Unglued.”[13] Kolak and Martin present a range of cases intended
to make the reader “walk across the bridge” from normal, reliable causes to no
cause. Before developing my positive account of causal conditions for identity,
I will critically examine Kolak and Martin’s examples, showing why I think that
a causal requirement should be retained. In order to have a clear foil against
which to argue, I will first need to ensure that their examples genuinely are
cases of the absence of causal connection.
The two examples purport to describe
a situation in which sequences of events follow one another just as they do in
our universe (as we understand it), but where there is no causal connection
between events. The first example offered by Kolak and Martin asks us to assume
that science one day discovers that the universe is causally just like the
situation in their MOC Match Example. This involves supposing that
the entire universe as we now know it flickers on
and off every instant. Between instants, some sort of cosmic randomizing device
creates an infinite number of sequences and then selects and conjoins with the
others only those which correspond in a normal way to the previous instant. In
that case, what exists at any one instant did not causally arise out of what
existed at the previous instant. It is not likely, to say the least, that
science will discover this. But if it did, would it make any difference to our
concept of personal identity, or would we go on just as before? We believe that
we would go on just as before, and that the fact that we would casts doubt on
the causal condition. (p.344)
This example fails to support the
claim that a causal connection of some kind is unnecessary. One problem we face
immediately is in understanding the workings of the universe as their example
describes it. I can see two significantly different ways of interpreting this
example. According to the first, the universe described has two main components:
A cosmic randomizing device (CRD) that seems to be the active component, and
the universe as we perceive it, a universe that really consists of consecutive
universe-slices created by the CRD. The CRD is quite distinct from the
universe-slices, being itself stable and not subject to the constant flickering
into and out of existence. If the CRD is to generate universe-slices in a
normal way, as posited, then it must contain an internal model at least as
complex as the universe. Without a model this complex the CRD would be unable
to “correctly” select the configuration that matched the previous
universe-slice and bring it into existence. In this situation it appears that
the universe as we perceive it—the sequence of universe-slices—is irrelevant to
the progression of events; everything of importance takes place within the CRD
where the model of the universe evolves smoothly. The external universe-slices
appear to be nothing more than epiphenomena; as such Kolak and Martin’s first
example becomes no different from their second, making my criticisms of that
example applicable to this.
Leaving this interpretation aside,
the example admits of another interpretation. The most natural interpretation,
and the one that accords with Kolak and Martin’s description of the MOC Match
Example from which it is adapted, is one where a causal connection is
maintained. Though one universe-slice does not directly cause the next one to match its configuration, each
subsequent slice is configured by the CRD because
that configuration matches the foregoing slice. If it weren’t for the earlier
universe-slice and its unique configuration, the CRD wouldn’t have generated
the later slice. If the CRD is causing successive states of the universe to
match up then the example does not
illustrate a situation where we believe persons to have persisted in the
absence of causal connections.
For the example to meet the no-cause
requirement we must reformulate it. The best way is to exclude the deus ex machina, the CRD, leaving the
example otherwise unaltered. Given this third interpretation, the example is
genuinely one where there are no causal connections between (qualitatively
non-identical) states of the universe.
Their second case asks us to
Suppose that what we ordinarily take to be causally
related stages of a continuing person are not related as causes and effects of each other but are rather epiphenomena
of some underlying process…
In our example it is our
bodies-plus-our-conscious-lives, the entire complexes of what most of us think
of as ourselves, that are causally impotent. This could happen if there were
very small temporal gaps between adjacent, “instantaneous” person-stages, and
no causal influence were transmitted across these gaps. Person-stages then
would merely appear to be causally related because the underlying process
insures [sic] that they give that appearance. Further, suppose that the
underlying process is not such that if we understood it, we would want to
include any of it into what we regard as a person.
The
description of this example is brief, leaving it open to interpretation.
However, only one interpretation is strictly consistent with the authors’
intent to remove all causal connection between person-stages. This
interpretation says:
During
the fleeting span of each instantaneous person-stage, no change occurs and no
causes exist. The underlying process removes each stage from existence and
replaces it with a slightly different stage, producing the appearance of change
and causal connection between stages.
This
makes the underlying process the Prime Mover and the clearly makes the stages
epiphenomena. There are causes operating, even though they are radically
different from those allowed by our current physical and biological models. In
these cases, between the stages of what we now think of as distinct, complete,
and continuing persons, there is no direct causal connection. If the
epiphenomenalist example turned out to be actual, Kolak and Martin claim that
such a discovery would not affect our everyday lives; “we would continue to
associate person-stages with persons in the same way that we do now.” (345) I
accept this conclusion; I would continue to believe in enduring persons.
Nevertheless, I deny that this example should lead us to reject causal conditions.
Not only does the example fail to justify throwing out all causal conditions,
it does not provide a reason to move beyond even the Narrow Reductionist’s
conservative position. Instead of rejecting causal conditions, we would have to
reformulate our conception of selves.
If we discovered such an underlying
process, and that process was recognizable as a person, then we would merely
have to accept that we are located differently than we had believed, just as
someone studying neuroscience might realize that consciousness resides in the
brain and not the heart. We could explain the illusion of being centered in our
heads as being due to the location of most of our senses, just as today’s
experimenters strapped into virtual reality gear have had the experience of
viewing their bodies from the outside, and feel that they are located at their
point of view. Relocation of the self is easy enough to imagine, but Kolak and
Martin explicitly rule it out. They stipulate that the underlying process is
not itself a person. This leaves us with the option of redrawing the boundaries
of persons. Rather than being located only in brains and bodies, as we had
thought, we would see ourselves as spread out between brains, bodies, and the
underlying process, wherever it was located. Perhaps the newly discovered
process is a field composed of a novel form of energy, spread out over miles,
overlapping with the fields of other persons. If so, we would come to see
ourselves, contrary to our untutored perceptions, as much larger, and as being
able to share space with another person in a way that our bodies cannot. The
continuing experiences of our reconceived selves would be caused not by the
brain, or not by the brain alone, but the underlying-process-brain combination.
Whereas today we believe one thought (or emotion, or intention) to follow from
another because of causes found in the brain, after the paradigm-shattering
discovery we would believe that thoughts follow one another because of causes
embedded in the underlying process. The causes were there all along, even
though we were in ignorance of them, therefore they are the normal and
(presumably) reliable causes. The discovery, startling as it would be, would
give us no reason to move even beyond the Narrow Reductionist View.
The foregoing might not satisfy
Kolak and Martin. They stipulate in their epiphenomenalist example not only
that the underlying process is not a person, but the much more restrictive
stipulation that “the underlying process is not such that if we understood it,
we would want to include any of it into what we regard as a person.” The underlying process is not a person, nor
is the process plus apparent (causally unconnected) person-stages. This move is
intended to force us to the view that, since our experience tells us that we
are continuing persons, persons must be able to persist despite an absence of
causal connection between person-stages. Syllogistically, the argument boils
down to this:
(1) We might discover that person-stages are
epiphenomena of an underlying (non-personlike) process and lack any causal
relation to one another.
(2)
In that situation we would still believe persons to exist.
Therefore, causal connection between person-stages
is not necessary for continuation of persons.
That is, we exist, possess
consciousness, and our experiences proceed in an orderly fashion, yet each
thought, each action, each feeling, each person-stage, has no causal relation
to the one before. If I accept Kolak and Martin’s analytical procedure, I must
reject one of the premises since I maintain the contrary of the conclusion.
Although I have reservations about the procedure I will not challenge it
because that would require arguments about the proper use of thought
experiments, and that would take me too far afield. Even accepting their procedure, I do not have
to accept the conclusion of the argument. If we were to uncover the truth of
this epiphenomenalist scenario, I would conclude that there were no persons.
Our notion of persons involves
enduring entities with certain properties such as (a capacity for) rationality,
responsibility, the ability to make choices, foresight, and (a capacity for)
self-restraint. None of these properties could exist in the epiphenomenalist
scenario. If I form an intention to do X at one moment, it can have no effect
whatsoever on whether I (or the appearance of a continuing “I”) later do X. The
succession of time-slices is determined by the non-personal underlying process
so that intentions will be followed by later actions that accord with those
intentions, yet there is no connection at all between the two. If I (the
momentary time-slice) had somehow formed a different intention, the underlying
process would nevertheless produce later time-slices according to its program.
Any decision I make at any moment can have no effect on “my” future actions.
Similarly, even if I had different experiences than I actually have, my
memories would be the same—as determined by the underlying process. If I were
to consider evidence different from that which I have, I would still reach the
same conclusion—the conclusion programmed by the underlying process. Nothing I
do now can make any difference to what I will do later. Nothing I have done in
the past can have any effect on what I choose to do now. The appearance of a
connection between actions and characteristics over time is only an appearance. The epiphenomenalist
scenario leaves no room for genuine choices, responsibility, or reasoning.
Without these characteristics the mere appearances left over do not remotely
satisfy our requirements for personhood.
Our experience seems to assure us
that there are persons and that this belief must persist after the
epiphenomenalist discovery. But our belief that we are persons, in the sense
standard for the term, is no more immune to revision and rejection than beliefs
about the rest of the world. Indeed, in the actual world, a substantial body of
research suggests we are systematically deluded about the nature of our
experience: see studies of blindsight, and experimentally-backed theories
asserting that we are never conscious of the present.[14]
I
conclude that this imaginary example should not lead us to abandon the causal
condition. Kolak and Martin are mistaken in their surprising assertion that
abandoning the causal condition in the face of this hypothetical discovery is a
conservative suggestion. If our successive conscious states were causally
unrelated, it is not true that everything else would be left intact. Nonsense
would be made of our notions of persons as agents, as responsible in any way
for our actions and thoughts, and of personal projects and goals of having any
value. Our intentions and memories and other characteristics would have nothing
to do with what we did. If we are satisfied that persons only persist in so far
as their phases are causally connected, we can move on to consider how liberal
we can be in allowing non-standard causal connections to count as maintaining a
person’s identity.
This argument supports a move at least up to the
Wide Reductionist View, and has been used by Nozick in defending the Closest
Continuer variant of Wide Reductionism. The essential idea is that we perceive
the continuation of objects according to a certain schema which is well
described by the closest continuer theory. This schema explains our intuitions
regarding the diachronic identity of changing objects. The unstated assumption
of Nozick’s point is that our conceptual understanding is strongly informed by
our perception. If our perception works according to a certain schema then this
provides some support to the belief that the schema well describes objects at
the conceptual level.
Nozick
describes experiments by psychologist Shimon Ullman intended to determine how
and when people classify discontinuous appearances as two appearances of the
same object and when as appearances of two different objects. An object was
shown moving in a straight line towards a screen and then disappearing behind
it. After a short time another object came out of the other end of the screen.
The angle of exit was varied, as well the object’s color, shape, and velocity.
The results of the experiments fitted the closest continuer hypothesis. For
example, if the object exited at a different angle, or after a delay, people
assumed that it had been struck behind the screen and was the same object. But
if two objects exited the screen, the one with the angle, velocity, etc., of
the entering object was thought to be the original object.
In
these judgements of continuity of the same object, it does not matter whether
the object is perceived continuously. Nozick thinks that these experiments
support both parts of the Closest Continuer theory: (a) That a later object Y
is the same as an earlier object X only if Y’s properties grow out of, are
causally dependent on X’s properties at the earlier time; (b) there is no other
Z at the later time that stands in a closer (or as close) relationship to X
than does Y.[15]
If
the argument from perception has weight it supports Wide Reductionism because
it supports the view that something is the same thing so long as it is similar
and continues sufficiently smoothly from an earlier phase of an object. It
seems not to matter that the qualities of the object are not spatio-temporally
continuous. However, as Nozick presents it, the perception argument rules out
the Extreme Interpretation of the Widest View since this rejects (a). This
argument gives some support to the Conservative Interpretation of the Widest
View. CIWR weakens the causal condition considerably by allowing quite indirect
causes to maintain identity. Certainly CIWR is compatible with the experimental
results: The subjects do not know what is happening behind the screen; perhaps
some unusual causal process occurs, but one that results in an exiting object
with a similar enough trajectory, velocity, or appearance to convince the
viewers of its continuity with the object that entered. Although compatible
with CIWR, these results do not provide convincing grounds for moving from the
Wide to the Widest Reductionist view. The experiment does not test how the
subjects’ responses might be effected if they were to consider the possibility
that something highly unusual had happened behind the screen. Perhaps the entering
object was instantaneously scanned then disintegrated, and an exactly similar
object created according to the information gleaned in the scan and put back on
the original object’s trajectory. Perhaps the experiments weakly support CIWR
in particular in that unusual causes like this could have been operating, yet the subjects still made the
judgements they did. However, the experiment was not designed to specifically
test reactions to such situations.
This
argument from perception is suggestive and may give some weight to the Wide and
even the Widest Reductionist Views, but it is not strong enough to give these
views sufficient support by itself. We might doubt that the operation of our
normal perception and conceptualization is a good guide to highly abstract
problems of identity as in personal identity. This is because of the Quinean
and Hansonian point that percepts must be conceptually interpreted, and
interpretations may be based on parochial experience and incorrect premises.
This first argument is therefore only a prelude to other more powerful
arguments.
Personal identity is
not defined by an entity’s continued possession of the same collection of
atoms. All versions of the psychological criterion of reductionism accept this,
as does Nagel’s physical same-brain criterion. The same-brain criterion requires
only that enough of one brain persists along a unitary spatio-temporal path.
The irrelevance of material persistence to personal identity or continuity is
supported by functionalism. Functionalism identifies beliefs, desires, and
other psychological states by their causal roles in an economy of such states.
My belief-that-p is distinguished by its relation to input, to other
psychological states, and to behavior.
Functionalism
supports psychological reductionism (Relation R) over physical reductionist
views like Nagel’s.[16] Nagel’s view is that I am essentially whatever is
normally the cause of psychological continuity, and this is a brain composed of
the usual proteins. Nagel sometimes seems to want to say that it is the brain
in certain states, rather than simply the whole brain, that is essential to
identity. But even that version of the same-brain criterion conflicts with
functionalism. According to functionalists, a belief-that-p might, in
principle, be instantiated in a human brain in one way, and in an animal’s,
extraterrestrial’s, or computer’s brain in different material. Even in a
single, continuous brain, certain neurons might be replaced over time with functionally
equivalent elements made of an entirely different material. Even if the
majority of the brain were eventually replaced in this manner, functionalism
says that the same beliefs, desires, intentions and memories would persist.
Since, according to psychological
reductionism, a person just is psychological connectedness and continuity,
functionalism supports some version of psychological reductionism.
Functionalism’s
type-token distinction cannot help us decide which variety of psychological reductionism is correct because
types at one level of abstraction can be seen as tokens at a different level of
abstraction. This means that we cannot be satisfied with simply identifying the
R-relation with the functional level rather than the material level. Doing this
will not distinguish any of the theories beyond Wide Reductionism from one
another since they can all claim to identify a self with a functional level of
description.
This
relativity of types and tokens can be illustrated as follows: A belief-that-p
is now tokened in me by group-of-atoms A. This group of atoms, at a particular
point in time, constitutes neuron group M. Here M, as constituted by specific
atoms, is a token. Over time the atoms constituting neuron group M change so
that M can be regarded as a type. Suppose that later my belief-that-p is
embodied a physically distinct neural circuit N in the same brain; at a higher level of abstraction the token is
now neuron group N and the type is the activation vector space[17] embodied in neuron group N. The activation vector
space might, at a later time, be instantiated in an artificial brain with
identical function to the biological organ, and where the vector space has
identical relations to other vector spaces in the artificial brain as it had when
instantiated in the original brain.
Functionalism
supports a move as far as Wide Reductionism but cannot decide between CIWR, and
EIWR. Functionalism gives conditions for the type-identity of cognitive states.
My belief-that-p in 1991 is type-identical with my belief-that-p in 1995 just
so long as both instances of belief-that-p have the same functional role.
According to psychological reductionism I am nothing more than the
connectedness and continuity of my psychological states. Thus, if a person is constituted
by an inter-related collection of psychological states each of which is
type-identical with an earlier person’s psychological states, the earlier and
later person are identical.
However
functionalism does not specify whether a break in the spatiotemporal continuity
of a person disrupts the type-identity of psychological states. The question
does not normally arise, since functionalism is a thesis about the type-identity of psychological states,
whereas the current issue is the continuing identity of an individual. The personal identity question and functionalism are
related because, as noted above, an individual over time (or before and after
teletransportation) can be viewed as a series of collections of type-identical
psychological states. Functionalism might be held to support only Wide
Reductionism, or also one of the Widest Reductionist views. Functionalism is
not able to decide between these theories since it does not address the issue
of spatiotemporal continuity; it only talks about type-identity between
different individuals, or between earlier and later instances of the same
spatiotemporally continuous individual. There is no obvious reason, however,
why it is not compatible with the more liberal reductionist views. All
discussions of functionalism assume spatiotemporal continuity since, in a world
as yet lacking teletransporters and practicing Universal Immortalists, there
are no instances of persons with spatiotemporal discontinuities.
Since
I want to defend CIWR, which allows identity to persist across spatiotemporal
discontinuities, I will now leave functionalism aside. Different support is
required to move beyond Wide Reductionism to the Widest Reductionist theories.
This next stage is important because many people’s intuitions rebel when
examples involve these discontinuities. Many of those who can accept My Brain Transplant and The Transporter are troubled by A Heroic Reconstruction, and cannot
accept either Omega Point Resurrection
or The Luckiest Person in the Universe
as cases of continuing personal identity. The following series of cases begins
with Parfit’s neurosurgeon example. Parfit uses that example to show the
irrelevance of spatiotemporal continuity. To begin, here is Parfit’s story:
In Case One,
the surgeon performs a hundred operations. In each of these, he removes a
hundredth part of my brain, and inserts a replica of this part. In Case Two, the surgeon follows a
different procedure. He first removes all the parts of my brain, and inserts
all of their replicas. (p.474)
In
both cases the matter embodying mental items is different after the operation
from what it is before. But we have seen that this does not concern us. In Case
One there is spatiotemporal continuity between the old embodiments. One small
part of the brain is removed at a time; the new part is attached to the brain
and becomes part of it before another piece is removed and exchanged.
Throughout Case One the same brain remains. In Case Two, if we require
spatio-temporal continuity for physical objects then the same brain does not
exist after the operation. The new brain is functionally identical to the old
one but is a different brain.
In
both of the cases there will later be a person whose brain will be exactly like
my present brain, and so that person will be psychologically continuous with
me. “And, in both cases, this
person’s brain will be composed of the very
same new components, each of which is a replica of some part of my brain.
The difference between the cases is merely the way in which these new parts are
inserted. It is a difference in the orderings of removals and insertions. In
Case One, the surgeon alternates between removing and inserting. In Case Two,
he does all the removing before the inserting.” (Parfit, p.475.)
The
example can be made even more compelling if we specify that in both cases I am
anesthetized before the operation. There is no difference in my experience
between the two cases. Now, how can the difference in the order of insertions
and removals be the difference between life and death? Why should it be vital
that the new parts are temporarily connected to the old parts? If the order of
insertions involved some further fact – perhaps a mystical force attaching only
to gradual insertions and removals – then the order would be significant. But
there is no further fact. The example can be varied by imagining an extremely
rapid robot surgeon who is able to remove and insert neurons so fast that the
new parts are connected to the old parts for only nanoseconds. This makes it
even more implausible to think that the continued existence of the same
physical brain is important.
There
is no significant difference between Case Two and The Transporter. Wide Reductionism and CIWR are therefore
supported. The reliability of the cause of psychological continuity is
irrelevant to the issue of identity. So long as all the parts of the brain are
put together so as to produce psychological continuity we have maintained
identity. The neurosurgeon might have changed her mind about finishing the
operation. Perhaps after removing all the neurons she was told that I am an
evil person and, being a utilitarian, she desisted from inserting the new
neurons in order to rid the world of an undesirable person. Or perhaps she had
a heart attack before inserting the new neurons. Many causes could stop the
insertion process and thereby terminate the R-relation. Yet, surely, if the
insertion does go ahead despite these
uncertainties we have no reason to withhold the judgment that I have survived
the procedure. It appears then, that this example supports our move at least as
far as CIWR; any cause of continuity is sufficient. It need not be reliable so
long as it does actually operate in any instance.
It
is hard to see any non-arbitrary way of stopping the move from Case One of the
gradual insertions and removals to Case Two with its absence of spatio-temporal
continuity or reliable cause. The lack of grounds for refusing to move from one
case to another is the negative case in favor of CIWR. The positive case is
that what we care about is the R‑relation (see the fourth argument,
“Series-Persons”, below). Normally we are concerned about the continuity of the
brain because normally such continuity is practically necessary to the
maintenance of the R-relation. These cases just emphasize what we already have
grounds to believe: that what matters is the R-relation and not its normal
carrier.
The
neurosurgeon cases are just one example of a slippery slope that moves us
irresistibly from intuitively plausible cases to those that are initially more
difficult. Many other slippery slopes could be constructed. For example, if the
opponent of CIWR tries to base his case on the reliability of the cause of continuity of the R-relation, we can
vary circumstances in such a way that the continuity of the brain becomes
unlikely. Brain continuity is never guaranteed: There are always strokes,
falls, speeding vehicles, and falling objects. Suppose the conditions of the
world changed so that the odds of brains surviving in one piece over the course
of a day became very much smaller. I doubt that anyone would then say that the
unreliability of my brain continuity meant that I was not the same person over
time even though I was lucky enough to avoid brain destruction longer than most
people. It would be tedious to construct more slippery slopes, so I will stick
with the neurosurgeon cases. Once we see that it is the R-relation that we
truly care about in these cases, we can see that many slippery slope moves
could be described to undermine arbitrary restrictions on the causes of
R-relation continuity.
My elaboration of Parfit’s neurosurgeon example
indicates the difficulty that will face anyone attempting to limit personal
identity within a normal causal or spatio-temporal framework. In examining
Nagel’s view that we are essentially our brains, Parfit adds further weight to
the foregoing conclusion. He demonstrates that even if we accept Nagel’s claim
that “I” and “me” refer to whatever actually makes possible my psychological
continuity, we can still reach the Wide Reductionist View. The argument
involves Nagel’s notion of a “series-person.” I will present Parfit’s argument
briefly since I have nothing to add to it.
Suppose
that the previous arguments are unsuccessful and that I am essentially my brain
and what matters to me is the continued existence of my brain. If this is what
persons essentially are I, as a person, cannot choose to take a different view
about what matters. But this leaves open another option. “While a person is, on
Nagel’s view, essentially a particular embodied brain, a series‑person is
potentially an R-related series of embodied brains.”[18] Nagel imagines a community in which everyone enters
a Scanning Replicator once a year. The Replicator destroys the person’s brain
and body and creates an exact Replica (except that it has not aged) who is
R-related to this person. Nagel says that it would be rational for the
series-persons of the community to use this Scanning Replicator and Parfit adds
that such series-persons could live forever if they made back-up blueprints
every day. Persons do not survive the Replicator but series-persons do.
If
Nagel is right that I am essentially my brain I cannot change my view about
what I am. But I can henceforth use pronouns to refer to series-persons. The
criterion of identity for persons is continuation of the brain but the
criterion for series-persons is Relation R with any cause (i.e., it is the same
as the criterion for persons if Nagel’s view is false). The words “I” and “me”
now refer not to the person Max More but to the series-person whose present
brain and body are the same as Max More’s brain and body. The previous sense of
“I” and “me” will henceforth be expressed by “old-I” and “old-me.”
Any
activity that I carry out is being carried out by two different individuals if Nagel’s view is correct. Although the
two of us both take the same actions at the same time we are distinct: If we go
through a teletransporter then old-me, the person, would be destroyed, but I
the series-person would continue. The series‑ person was not brought into
existence by the invention of the concept. He has existed for as long as
old-me, the person. Unless teletransportation, uploading of my mind into a
computer, etc., become possible within my lifetime, I, the series-person, will
also cease to exist at the same time as old-me.
Supposing
Nagel’s view to be true, what matters for old-me is the continued existence of
my present brain. Despite this we can believe that what really matters is
relation R, not brain continuity.
Relation R is what matters for me, the series-person. Why speak and think as a
series-person rather than a person? Consider another concept of Nagel’s: The day-person. Essential to the existence
of a day-person is an uninterrupted stream of consciousness. Sleep or
anaesthesia is death for a day-person. The concept of a day-person applies to
reality but carves up reality into unimportant boundaries. We care about
relation R and not the noninterruption of consciousness. The concept of a
day-person is in this way inferior to the concept of a person. But then, if
Nagel’s view is true, the concept of a person is inferior to that of a
series-person in a similar way. The concept of a series-person appeals to what
is more important—relation R.
If
Nagel’s view is false, the distinction between persons and series-persons is
unimportant. Our criterion of identity will fail to cover many imaginary cases
and some actual cases[19] (such as people with divided hemispheres). Since
non-reductionism is false, questions about identity in those cases are empty.
We can give answers to these questions by extending our criterion of identity,
such as by making the criterion the non-branching holding of Relation R. On
that criterion persons are
series-persons and the distinction disappears. So, if Nagel’s view is false,
the criterion for identity of persons allows persons to survive
teletransportation. If Nagel’s view is true, persons cannot survive
teletransportation but then series-persons can proclaim their existence and use
pronouns to refer to themselves. Since the concept of a series-person would
carve up reality in less arbitrary ways this would be an improvement.
Consideration
of series-persons therefore supports the Wide Reductionist View. It can easily
also support the Widest View if we alter the example a little. In Nagel’s
example, each year people enter a Scanning Replicator. In the altered example,
we introduce an unreliable element of choice into the situation. Each person
goes into the Replicator each year with the hope of being scanned, destroyed,
and replicated in a de-aged body. However, the Scanning Replicators are
controlled by a sect of technocrats who have taken it upon themselves to
“improve society” by ending the existence of those they believe fail to meet
their criteria for “good citizens.” They make these decisions after an
individual has been scanned and destroyed but before they are replicated. If
they decide against someone, their stored pattern information is randomized or
overwritten. The process now is unreliable because it involves a choice. If the
people use “I” to refer to series-persons, they will still survive the scanning
and replicating process if those controlling it allow them to make it through.
Altered in this way, the series-person argument supports not only the Wide View
but also the Widest Reductionist View.
Despite the arguments and cases I have presented,
doubt may linger over the case of A
Heroic Reconstruction. Where the causal connection between phases of a
person is highly roundabout and unreliable as in AHR, it may be hard to believe
that CIWR is true. Even if the arguments I have given together constitute a
strong case for this position, conflicting intuitions are likely to keep rising
from the grave to haunt us whenever we forget about the arguments and thought
experiments. As Hume noted, there are some philosophical views which go so much
against the grain that when we leave the attentive reflection that convinced us
of their truth we find ourselves once again feeling that a view is wrong even
though we cannot support our intuition. (This can be just as true of physical
theories such as relativity or the rejection of geocentrism.) I have found that
my intuitions about the more difficult cases have gradually shifted. As the
theoretical framework of the Widest View became embedded in my thinking my
intuitive reactions to bizarre cases like AHR increasingly conformed to the
theory.
In
this final section I want to further undermine intuitions that conflict with
the theory by explaining why they exist. Intuitions arise because of
well-entrenched assumptions formed often unconsciously or implicitly. If it can
be shown that a certain intuition arises because it is normally well-grounded,
but that it becomes over‑generalized, then we can undermine the reasonableness
of forming beliefs on that intuitive reaction in cases outside its boundaries
of applicability.
For
example, cognitive psychologists have demonstrated that humans typically use a
few heuristic rules such as the representativeness and availability heuristics
to make judgements in a wide range of cases. These heuristics work well much of
the time but occasionally lead us to the wrong conclusions, as can be
demonstrated by more sophisticated reasoning procedures such as probability
theory. Once we have explained why we use the heuristics, and once we have
defined their limited domain of applicability, we can deny any weight to
intuitive judgements where they stray beyond their effective domain. Similarly,
once we have Einsteinian and quantum mechanical physics—a physics well-grounded
in theory and observation—we need not give weight to the Newtonian intuitions
naturally derived from our normal experience of medium-sized objects with
medium velocities.
A
common intuitive response when considering the role of causation in personal
identity is that we only survive if the normal cause of our psychological
continuity is maintained. For many educated people, this means they feel that
the brain (or enough of the brain) must persist. For others, it means that that
their “soul” must continue to exist, or perhaps that their soul must remain
embodied. Especially for those many people who do not spend time thinking
imaginatively about fictional or possible future scenarios, the very fact that,
say, the brain is normally the cause
of psychological continuity, is enough to wear deep grooves into their
intuitions.
In
all real cases that we have ever encountered, and perhaps in all cases that we
ever shall encounter, normal and direct causal connections are involved in the maintenance of psychological continuity and
connectedness. Explanations of why I am much as I was a few minutes ago, and
explanations of why I have changed somewhat from the way I was a year ago,
always in fact involve causal explanations of a familiar kind. The relation R
is, as a current matter of fact, embodied in brains and bodies. In the world as
it is and always has been the standard physical causes we see in brains and
bodies are practically essential to R-relatedness over time.
Disruptive
intervention in the causal chain, such as brain injury or destruction, or the
degeneration of aging, terminates the R-relation. It is understandable that we
are so concerned to ensure that the appropriate causes continue to operate. We
know that if our brains decay or are destroyed then we go with them. This fact
explains the attraction not only of the belief that normal, direct, and
reliable causal connection is necessary to personal identity but also the
appeal of the physical criterion of personal identity.
However,
as all the foregoing arguments have established, what really matters is
R-relatedness. We care about psychological continuity and connectedness. If
this can be secured by means other than the usual then we should be satisfied.
Not so many years ago the idea of having your body disassembled, beamed across
space, and reassembled would have terrified just about everyone. It would have
been thought of as death. Now, very many people have got used to the idea by
seeing it portrayed on Star Trek, by
reading discussions of personal identity, or other sources, and the imaginary
process is usually thought of as a means of travelling rather than as a means
of dying. Many of these people, if they considered it, might therefore agree to
the Wide Reductionist View, granting personal identity so long as there is some
causal connection between the earlier and later persons. Unlike previous
generations they do not think a normal cause is essential.
The
third case I described, A Heroic
Reconstruction, will still upset many people, but the reason for this, is I
think, that they are not used to considering such events. If someone were to
produce a popular science fiction TV series based around the reconstructionist
attempts of the Universal Immortalists many more people would gradually come to
accept this as a way of surviving.
Our
intuitions are explained by our concern that our psychological connectedness
and continuity be maintained. We are more uncomfortable about using a
transporter than about normal continuity because we find it easy to imagine the
transporter malfunctioning and leaving our disassembled atoms spread across
space. We have no theoretical grounds for rejecting abnormal or unreliable
causes of R-relatedness. Our concern is a perfectly reasonable practical concern. I will not place my
trust in an unreliable cause if I can do better. If I have a choice of
extending my lifespan by a proven and reliable medical technology, I will
obviously choose that over the possibility that I might one day be reconstructed
by Universal Immortalists. However, what I care about is continuing to exist,
not the means of this continuation except
in so far as this is a practical question. If psychological continuity is
maintained by a more unlikely method I will not complain. Just as in the
neurosurgeon case, I would much prefer that my neurosurgeon did not have a
heart attack, but if she did and her colleague managed to bring about the same
result then I would still have survived even though survival by that method was
much less likely.
We
can conclude then, that while a normal, direct, or reliable causal connection
between earlier and later persons may be practically necessary for them to be
the same person, this is not conceptually or theoretically necessary. We care
about the continuation of our personality, our goals, projects, values,
memories, beliefs. Since normal, direct, reliable causal connections are
standardly necessary to this kind of continuation we will also care about those
kinds of connections instrumentally. But where standard kinds of causal
connectedness turn out in a particular case to have been unnecessary to
psychological continuity, we should realize that standard causal connections
and psychological connectedness have come apart, and that it is the latter that
should concern us. Having argued in favor of CIWR as the causal criterion to
satisfy if we are to continue to exist, I will now turn to the question of when
we cease to exist. Applying the Widest Reductionist View to the concept of and
criteria for death shows up the deficiencies in the criteria currently used.
[1]Possibly also some accompanying
physical features—see Chapter on “Technological Transformation and Assimilation.”
[2]Armstrong develops this distinction in “Identity
Through Time” in Van Inwagen (ed), Time
and Cause.
[3]For instance in Parfit (1971) he says we can
“redescribe a person’s life as the history of a series of successive selves.”
[4]Hans Moravec, in Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human
Intelligence (recently supported in this thesis by Marvin Minsky), argues
that the coming decades will see a transfer of human personalities into a
synthetic hardware capable of running thousands to millions of times faster. If
this happens, then a later self-stage only a year older in objective time could
have developed so much that its earlier phases constituted a tiny portion of
it.
[5] Parfit, 1984, p.206.
[6] Parfit, ibid, p.207.
[7] Parfit, ibid, p.208
[8] Nozick, 1981, p.39.
[9] Except that Nozick allows the
possibility that features other than psychological ones may be constitutive of
identity (p.69). I will examine the question of what features other than
psychological we might include in the conditions for identity in the chapter
“Technological Transformation and Assimilation.”
[10] Nozick, p.43.
[12] Of course dualists and idealists
may also believe the universe to be self-sustaining: They may be deists rather
than theists.
[13]Kolak and Martin (1987).
[14]L. Weiskrantz, 1986, Blindsight. B. Libet, Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
1985,1987, 1989.
[15] This is a paraphrase of Nozick,
p.36-37.
[16] Parfit provides several strong
considerations against Nagel’s brain criterion for identity in Parfit, 1984, S.93 and Appendix D.
[17] For a clear explanation of
activation vector spaces and connectionist views of concept formation and
learning see “On the Nature of Theories: A Neurocomputational Perspective,” and
“On the Nature of Explanation: A PDP Approach,” in Paul M. Churchland, 1989.
[18] Parfit, p.289-290.
[19] Christine Korsgaard summarizes
these cases in “Personal Identity and the Unity of Agency,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, Spring
1989, pp. 104-105.
No comments:
Post a Comment